dunnettreader + causation 54
List
july 2017 by dunnettreader
Political science is divided between methodological individualists, who seek to explain political phenomena by reference to individuals and their interactions, and holists (or nonreductionists), who consider some higher-level social entities or properties such as states, institutions, or cultures ontologically or causally significant. We propose a reconciliation between these two perspectives, building on related work in philosophy. After laying out a taxonomy of different variants of each view, we observe that (i) although political phenomena result from underlying individual attitudes and behavior, individual-level descriptions do not always capture all explanatorily salient properties, and (ii) nonreductionistic explanations are mandated when social regularities are robust to changes in their individual-level realization. We characterize the dividing line between phenomena requiring nonreductionistic explanation and phenomena permitting individualistic explanation and give examples from the study of ethnic conflicts, social-network theory, and international-relations theory. - downloaded via iphone to Dbox
positivism
emergence
reductionism
causation-social
critical_realism
epistemology-social
article
methodology
jstor
social_history
causation
downloaded
philosophy_of_social_science
individualism-methodology
july 2017 by dunnettreader
Andrew Gelman - The problems with p-values are not just with p-values: My comments on the recent ASA statement - March 2016
march 2016 by dunnettreader
His blog Statistical Modeling, Causal Inference, and Social Science -- The American Statistical Association just released a committee report on the use of p-values. I was one of the members of the committee but I did not write the…
Instapaper
quantitative_methods
statistics
social_sciences
uncertainty
probability
methodology-quantitative
scientific_culture
research
publishing-academic
pharma
causation
evidence
from instapaper
march 2016 by dunnettreader
E.J.Lowe, review essay. - Locke: Compatibilist Event-Causalist or Libertarian Substance-Causalist? (2004) | JSTOR - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research
january 2016 by dunnettreader
Review essay - Yaffe, G., 2000. Liberty Worth the Name: Locke on Free Agency. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research
Vol. 68, No. 3 (May, 2004), pp. 688-701 - downloaded to iPhone - DBOX
agency
reviews
free_will
jstor
downloaded
Locke-Essay
intellectual_history
causation
Vol. 68, No. 3 (May, 2004), pp. 688-701 - downloaded to iPhone - DBOX
january 2016 by dunnettreader
Kuni Sakamoto - Pierre Gassendi's Reception of Keplerian Ideas | JSTOR Journal of the History of Ideas (Jan 2009)
january 2016 by dunnettreader
The German Hercules's Heir: Pierre Gassendi's Reception of Keplerian Ideas -- Journal of the History of Ideas, Vol. 70, No. 1 (Jan., 2009), pp. 69-91 -- big interesting bibliography -- downloaded pdf to Note
article
jstor
intellectual_history
16thC
17thC
ancient_philosophy
natural_philosophy
natural_history
Plato
Aristotle
Pliny_the_Elder
Albert_Magnus
medieval_philosophy
astronomy
astrology
cosmology
Kepler
Gassendi
atomism
generation
divine_intellect
causation
mathematization
bibliography
downloaded
january 2016 by dunnettreader
Adam Takahashi - Nature, Formative Power and Intellect in the Natural Philosophy of Albert the Great | JSTOR - Early Science and Medicine (2008)
january 2016 by dunnettreader
Early Science and Medicine, Vol. 13, No. 5 (2008), pp. 451-481 -- The Dominican theologian Albert the Great (ca. 1200-1280) was one of the first to investigate into the system of the world on the basis of an acquaintance with the entire Aristotelian corpus, which he read under the influence of Islamic philosophers. The present study aims to understand the core of Albert's natural philosophy. Albert's emblematic phrase, "every work of nature is the work of intelligence" (omne opus naturae est opus intelligentiae), expresses the conviction that natural things are produced by the intellects that move the celestial bodies, just as houses are made by architects moving their instruments. Albert tried to fathom the secret of generation of natural things with his novel notion of "formative power" (virtus formativa), which flows from the celestial intellects into the sublunary elements. His conception of the natural world represents an alternative to the dominant medieval view on the relationship between the artificial and the natural. -- large bibliography of secondary sources post WWII -- downloaded pdf to Note
article
jstor
intellectual_history
medieval_philosophy
13thC
Albert_Magnus
natural_philosophy
Aristotle
Aristotelian
causation
cosmology
laws_of_nature
divine_intellect
generation
bibliography
downloaded
january 2016 by dunnettreader
Philip Ball - Why story is used to explain symphonies and sport matches - Aeon
november 2015 by dunnettreader
It’s a movie classic. The lovers are out for a walk when a villain dashes out of his house and starts fighting the man. The woman takes refuge in the house;…
neuroscience
evo_psych
narrative
complexity
causation
cognitive_bias
cognition
cognition-social
epistemology-naturalism
Instapaper
from instapaper
november 2015 by dunnettreader
G. A. Wells - Herder's Determinism | JSTOR - Journal of the History of Ideas (1958)
october 2015 by dunnettreader
Journal of the History of Ideas, Vol. 19, No. 1 (Jan., 1958), pp. 105-113 -- see also his follow up on how the German historicist school (Meinecke et al) found what they wanted to in Herder's works, distorting Herder in the process -- downloaded pdf to Note
article
jstor
intellectual_history
historiography
historiography-18thC
German_scholars
historicism
relativism
causation
causation-social
Herder
determinism
downloaded
october 2015 by dunnettreader
Jared P. Friedman and Anthony I. Jack - Mapping cognitive structure onto philosophical debate re problems of consciousness, free will and ethics | Minds Online - Sept 2015 - Session 1 - Social Cognition
september 2015 by dunnettreader
Mapping cognitive structure onto the landscape of philosophical debate: An empirical framework with relevance to problems of consciousness, free will and ethics -- Department of Philosophy and Inamori International Center for Ethics and Excellence, Case Western Reserve University -- There are some seemingly intractable questions that have remained at the heart of philosophical discourse since they were first asked. Is the mind distinct from the brain or are we just physical stuff? Are we autonomous agents or merely at the mercy of the causal and mechanistic laws of nature? When, if ever, is it acceptable to sacrifice one for the greater good of many? That these questions have remained at the heart of philosophy for so long, and that their ‘solutions’ (e.g., monism vs. dualism) seem to be incommensurable with each other, strikes us as enigmatic. Might the intractable nature of these and other appropriately identified problems reflect something peculiar about us rather than something peculiar about the way the world is? (...) This account maintains that the difficulties reconciling markedly different philosophical responses to these three questions arise from an unavoidable tension between two anatomically independent and functionally inhibitory neural networks, both of which are essential to human understanding. This account is motivated by the observation that both philosophers and non-philosophers experience difficulty in reconciling competing responses to these questions. -- downloaded pdf to Note
paper
conference
cognition
antimonies
consciousness
mind-body
neuroscience
determinism
free_will
naturalism
physicalism
reductionism
causation
moral_philosophy
metaethics
intuitions
brain
experimental_philosophy
analytical_philosophy
James_William
monism
dualism
downloaded
september 2015 by dunnettreader
Raymond BOUDON - LA RATIONALITÉ DU RELIGIEUX SELON MAX WEBER | JSTOR - L'Année sociologique - Vol. 51, No. 1 (2001), pp. 9-50
may 2015 by dunnettreader
LA RATIONALITÉ DU RELIGIEUX SELON MAX WEBER - L'Année sociologique (1940/1948-), Troisième série, Vol. 51, No. 1 (2001), pp. 9-50 -- One of the most striking features of Weber's writings on religion is the frequency with which he uses the word rationality. This derives from the metatheory grounding in his mind the interpretative method. This metatheory asserts that the meaning to an individual of his beliefs should be seen as the main cause explaining why he endorses them. Weber's religion sociology owes its strength to this theoretical framework. His « rational » conception of religious beliefs does not imply that these beliefs derive from deliberation. They are rather transmitted to the social subject in the course of his socialisation. But they are accepted only if they are perceived by the subject as grounded. These principles inspire Weber's pages on magical beliefs, on animism, on the great religions, on the diffusion of monotheism, on theodicy or the world disenchantment. He shows that religious thinking cares on coherence, tends to verify and falsify religious dogmas by confronting them with observable facts. He develops a complex version of evolutionism, explaining the cases of irreversibility registered by the history of religions, but avoiding any fatalism. He rejects any depth psychology and any causalist psychology in his sociology of religion, the common rational psychology being the only one that can be easily made compatible with the notion of "Verstehende Soziologie", i.e. of « interpretative sociology ». Weber analyses the evolution of religious ideas supposing that they follow the same mechanisms as the evolution of ideas in other domains, as law, economics or science. -- downloaded pdf to Note
article
jstor
sociology_of_religion
Weber
Boudon
rationality
causation
causation-social
religious_history
religious_belief
religious_culture
hermeneutics
social_theory
socialization
social_process
rationality-bounded
disenchantment
causation-evolutionary
psychology
mechanisms-social_theory
downloaded
may 2015 by dunnettreader
Neil Sinhababu - The Humean Theory of Motivation Reformulated and Defended | JSTOR - The Philosophical Review Vol. 118, No. 4 (OCTOBER 2009), pp. 465-500
may 2015 by dunnettreader
Looks useful for discussion of how previous formulations work and objections - not many references in bibliography however -- downloaded pdf to Note
article
jstor
human_nature
moral_philosophy
moral_psychology
moral_sentiments
passions
reason
rationality
decision_theory
action-theory
motivation
causation
Hume
Hume-causation
Hume-ethics
downloaded
may 2015 by dunnettreader
Sven Ove Hansson -Risk (updated 2011) | Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
february 2015 by dunnettreader
Since the 1970s, studies of risk have grown into a major interdisciplinary field of research. Although relatively few philosophers have focused their work on risk, there are important connections between risk studies and several philosophical subdisciplines. This entry summarizes the most well-developed of these connections and introduces some of the major topics in the philosophy of risk. It consists of six sections dealing with the definition of risk and with treatments of risk related to epistemology, the philosophy of science, the philosophy of technology, ethics, and the philosophy of economics.
1. Defining risk [including objective vs subjective and risk vs uncertainty - the latter comparison mostly formalized in decision tgeory]
2. Epistemology
3. Philosophy of science
4. Philosophy of technology
5. Ethics
6. Risk in economic analysis
Related Entries -- causation: in the law | causation: probabilistic | consequentialism | contractarianism | economics, philosophy of | game theory | luck: justice and bad luck | scientific knowledge: social dimensions of | technology, philosophy of
philosophy
epistemology
epistemology-social
epistemology-moral
causation
causation-social
probability
Bayesian
moral_philosophy
utilitarianism
utility
rights-legal
game_theory
philosophy_of_science
philosophy_of_social_science
economic_theory
behavioral_economics
financial_economics
sociology_of_knowledge
philosophy_of_law
risk
risk-mitigation
risk_management
uncertainty
rational_choice
rationality-economics
1. Defining risk [including objective vs subjective and risk vs uncertainty - the latter comparison mostly formalized in decision tgeory]
2. Epistemology
3. Philosophy of science
4. Philosophy of technology
5. Ethics
6. Risk in economic analysis
Related Entries -- causation: in the law | causation: probabilistic | consequentialism | contractarianism | economics, philosophy of | game theory | luck: justice and bad luck | scientific knowledge: social dimensions of | technology, philosophy of
february 2015 by dunnettreader
Seamus Bradley Imprecise Probabilities (Dec 2014) | Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
february 2015 by dunnettreader
It has been argued that imprecise probabilities are a natural and intuitive way of overcoming some of the issues with orthodox precise probabilities. Models of this type have a long pedigree, and interest in such models has been growing in recent years. This article introduces the theory of imprecise probabilities, discusses the motivations for their use and their possible advantages over the standard precise model. It then discusses some philosophical issues raised by this model. There is also a historical appendix which provides an overview of some important thinkers who appear sympathetic to imprecise probabilities. *-* Related Entries -- belief, formal representations of | epistemic utility arguments for probabilism | epistemology: Bayesian | probability, interpretations of | rational choice, normative: expected utility | statistics, philosophy of | vagueness
epistemology
philosophy_of_science
technology
probability
risk
uncertainty
rational_choice
rationality-economics
rationality
rationality-bounded
statistics
Bayesian
linguistics
causation
causation-social
causation-evolutionary
complexity
complex_adaptive_systems
utility
behavioral_economics
behavioralism
neuroscience
vagueness
february 2015 by dunnettreader
Special Issue: Microfinance -- AEAweb: American Economic Journal: Applied Economics Vol. 7 No.1, Jan 2015
january 2015 by dunnettreader
Abstract of introductory article -- Causal evidence on microcredit impacts informs theory, practice, and debates about its effectiveness as a development tool. The six randomized evaluations in this volume use a variety of sampling, data collection, experimental design, and econometric strategies to identify causal effects of expanded access to microcredit on borrowers and/or communities. These methods are deployed across an impressive range of locations—six countries on four continents, urban and rural areas—borrower characteristics, loan characteristics, and lender characteristics. Summarizing and interpreting results across studies, we note a consistent pattern of modestly positive, but not transformative, effects. We also discuss directions for future research. -- broad conclusion to be expected contra the hype -- but focus still seems to be on *credit* (with assumptions re micro and SME entrepreneurs and business formation) rather than access to services -- also question whether the former Yugoslavia study really dealt with "micro", likely the sort of labeling of SMEs as micro like Aftab's programs
journals-academic
article
paywall
microfinance
access_to_finance
development
economic_growth
economic_sociology
development-impact
RCT
econometrics
causation
causation-social
financial_sector_development
financial_economics
financial_access
institutional_economics
banking
credit
financial_innovation
SMEs
access_to_services
EF-add
january 2015 by dunnettreader
Kevin Meeker, review - Frederick F. Schmitt, Hume's Epistemology in the Treatise (OUP) // Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews // September 09, 2014
september 2014 by dunnettreader
This scholarly and philosophically rich treatment of Hume's epistemology furnishes a clear and comprehensive reading of Hume as a reliabilist about justified belief that is reminiscent of Alvin Goldman's naturalistic epistemology. One might worry that this is simply an anachronistic attempt to impose contemporary categories on Hume. One need not entertain such worries. ...he carefully connects Hume's concepts to contemporary ones and considerable attention relating Hume's views to Descartes, Malebranche, Newton and especially Locke. The book contains four major "divisions", and preceding the first division is a crucial chapter detailing the epistemological framework for this study -- In the first division, Schmitt notes that epistemologists from Plato's time have distinguished between knowledge and probability/belief/opinion - they have differed, though, on how to understand causal inferences in terms of this dichotomy. For Schmitt, although Hume mostly follows Locke's way of drawing the knowledge/probability distinction, Hume departs from Locke in wresting causal inferences from the domain of knowledge and placing them in the category of probability. According to Schmitt, Hume confronts this problem by arguing that knowledge and proofs produced by causal inferences are both types of justified belief because they are both forms of reliable belief. So there is no great gap between the epistemic status of knowledge and causal inferences. -- I hope that by now it is clear that the naturalistic, reliabilist epistemology that he attributes to Hume stands in stark contrast to the sceptical reading of Hume, according to which beliefs lack epistemic justification. -- copied full review to Evernote - put in Millican Treatise notebook
books
reviews
intellectual_history
17thC
18thC
Hume
epistemology
Descartes
Malebranche
Newton
Locke
Goldman_Alvin
scepticism
causation
epistemology-naturalism
inference
demonstration
fallibility
Evernote
september 2014 by dunnettreader
Charlie Huenemann, review - Matthew J. Kisner and Andrew Youpa (eds.), Essays on Spinoza's Ethical Theory (OUP) // Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews // September 09, 2014
september 2014 by dunnettreader
This volume presents a cohesive and engaging set of essays, converging on the question: was Spinoza frowning or smiling? ...as he surveyed the wide range of human moral phenomena, did he merely bemoan our superstitious beliefs and ignorant behaviors? Or did he see some of it as truly virtuous? But how can anything be virtuous, if all human actions are completely determined by an infinite substance that doesn't give a damn what happens? --...Charles Jarrett's essay forcefully presents the challenges of finding genuine morality in Spinoza's philosophy. As Jarrett reads him, Spinoza left himself no room to construct a meaningful "ideal" of human behavior. Indeed, "good" itself is misleading, as Spinoza "advocates or recommends that we take a perspective from which good and evil cannot be conceived. He thus seems... to advocate, a transcendence of ethics". -- Several essays take up Jarrett's challenge. -- Some of the essays are concerned with saving the possibility of Spinoza's morality from other doctrines he espoused. Michael LeBuffe ("Necessity and the Commands of Reason in the Ethics") -- Karolina Hübner rescues meaningful discourse about humanity as a whole in the face of Spinoza's disdain for universals. Eugene Marshall ("Man is a God to Man: How Humans can be Adequate Causes") defends the intelligibility, within Spinoza's determinism, that some actions can be autonomous and hence "free". -- Some of the essays provide broad and masterful perspective... meditations on the nature and significance of Spinoza's ethical project. -- A final trio of essays connects Spinoza's morality with the claims regarding "eternity" in Part V of the Ethics. These are especially welcome, as Spinoza's mystical claims are sometimes treated as an embarrassment or as a separate island of befuddlement. -- there is not a single clunker in the lot. The introduction is a thoughtful overview of the terrain that also provides a useful integration of the chapters that follow. If you are studying Spinoza's ethical theory, you need this book.
books
reviews
intellectual_history
17thC
Spinoza
metaphysics
moral_philosophy
determinism
free_will
causation
good
evil
infinity
virtue
september 2014 by dunnettreader
Jeffrey K. McDonough, review - Justin E. H. Smith, Divine Machines: Leibniz and the Sciences of Life // Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews // April 17, 2012
september 2014 by dunnettreader
Justin E. H. Smith, Divine Machines: Leibniz and the Sciences of Life, Princeton University Press, 2011, 392pp., $45.00 (hbk), ISBN 9780691141787.
Reviewed by Jeffrey K. McDonough, Harvard University -- It is widely recognized that Leibniz's philosophical thought is deeply influenced by the mathematics, physics and philosophical theology of his era. Justin E. H. Smith's Divine Machines argues that many of Leibniz's most central philosophical doctrines are similarly bound up with the life sciences of his time, where the "life sciences" are understood very broadly to include fields as diverse as alchemy, medicine, taxonomy, and paleontology. Smith's groundbreaking exploration represents an important contribution to our understanding of both Leibniz's philosophy and the study of life in the early modern era. It is to be recommended to historians, philosophers, and historians of philosophy alike. Below I highlight four central topics in Smith's book, raising some reservations along the way.
books
reviews
kindle-available
intellectual_history
17thC
Leibniz
history_of_science
philosophy_of_science
metaphysics
monads
causation
species
teleology
anatomy
biology
medicine
microscope
fossils
reproduction
theodicy
creation
mechanism
organism
Reviewed by Jeffrey K. McDonough, Harvard University -- It is widely recognized that Leibniz's philosophical thought is deeply influenced by the mathematics, physics and philosophical theology of his era. Justin E. H. Smith's Divine Machines argues that many of Leibniz's most central philosophical doctrines are similarly bound up with the life sciences of his time, where the "life sciences" are understood very broadly to include fields as diverse as alchemy, medicine, taxonomy, and paleontology. Smith's groundbreaking exploration represents an important contribution to our understanding of both Leibniz's philosophy and the study of life in the early modern era. It is to be recommended to historians, philosophers, and historians of philosophy alike. Below I highlight four central topics in Smith's book, raising some reservations along the way.
september 2014 by dunnettreader
Jeff McDonough - The Heyday of Teleology and Early Modern Philosophy" in Early Modern Philosophy Reconsidered, ed. John Carriero, Midwest Studies in Philosophy (35) 2011: 179-204
september 2014 by dunnettreader
"The Heyday of Teleology and Early Modern Philosophy" in Early Modern Philosophy Reconsidered, ed. John Carriero, Midwest Studies in Philosophy (35) 2011: 179-204. -- This paper argues that the standa...
article
Intellectual_history
history_of_science
philosophy_of_science
metaphysics
causation
teleology
ancient_philosophy
scholastics
17thC
Spinoza
Leibniz
good
downloaded
EF-add
from notes
september 2014 by dunnettreader
Jeff McDonough's CV - Harvard University - Philosophy Department
september 2014 by dunnettreader
Areas of Specialization: Early Modern Philosophy, History and Philosophy of Science. -- Areas of Competence:Medieval Philosophy, Metaphysics, Philosophy of Religion -- papers, conference presentations focus on Leibniz with some Berkeley, Hume
academia
intellectual_history
history_of_science
philosophy_of_science
metaphysics
philosophy_of_religion
17thC
18thC
Leibniz
Berkeley
causation
teleology
theodicy
Descartes
Spinoza
Hume
Malebranche
bibliography
september 2014 by dunnettreader
Richard Marshall interview - Jeffrey K. McDonough -Leibniz, Berkeley, Kant, Frege; bees, toasters and Julius Caesar » 3:AM Magazine - September 2014
september 2014 by dunnettreader
Good overview of different approaches to Leibniz. Causation and relation of divine and creaturely activity - Scholastics, Berkeley, Malebranche, Leibniz. Difference between Malebranche and Berkeley’s idealism. Kant on refutation of idealism re Cartesian scepticism of external world.
intellectual_history
17thC
18thC
Leibniz
Berkeley
Malebranche
Kant
substance
metaphysics
causation
teleology
theodicy
creation
mind-body
volition
mechanism
physics
philosophy_of_science
history_of_science
optics
idealism
scepticism
EF-add
september 2014 by dunnettreader
George F.R. Ellis | Personal Page
september 2014 by dunnettreader
Links to extensive number of books he has authored or co-authored and to speeches and papers -- Teaching and research interests: *-* General Relativity theory and its application to the study of the large-scale structure of the universe (cosmology). *-* The history and philosophy of cosmology. *-* Complex systems and emergence of complexity. *- * The human brain and behaviour. *-* Science policy, developmental issues. *-* Science and mathematics education. *-* The relation of science to religion.
philosophy_of_science
philosophy_of_religion
cosmology
physics
neuroscience
mind
mind-body
reductionism
causation
emergence
complexity
systems_theory
systems-complex_adaptive
science-and-religion
EF-add
september 2014 by dunnettreader
Trevor A. Harley - History lessons: what can we learn about history? | Rethinking History Vol. 18, Iss. 3, 2014 - Taylor & Francis Online
august 2014 by dunnettreader
What can we learn from the past? This paper examines the nature of the past and discusses the extent to which historical outcomes are robust over different starting conditions, using primarily the example of the origin of the Great War. It reviews the mathematical and psychological literature on complexity theory, and considers the idea that history can indeed in some circumstances be robust across initial conditions. I introduce the notion of a dynamic historical attractor to account for the way in which the past unfolds over time, and relate dynamic attractors to post-modern approaches to historical interpretation. -- Keywords: complexity, chaos, dynamic historical attractors, alternative histories, causality, narrative, post-modernism -- T&F paywall
article
paywall
historiography
causation-social
causation
complexity
chaos_theory
dynamic_attractors
counterfactuals
narrative
narrative-contested
postmodern
WWI
contingency
social_theory
EF-add
august 2014 by dunnettreader
Lucy Allais - Intrinsic Natures: A Critique of Langton on Kant | JSTOR: Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, Vol. 73, No. 1 (Jul., 2006), pp. 143-169
august 2014 by dunnettreader
This paper argues that there is an important respect in which Rae Langton's recent interpretation of Kant is correct: Kant's claim that we cannot know things in themselves should be understood as the claim that we cannot know the intrinsic nature of things. However, I dispute Langton's account of intrinsic properties, and therefore her version of what this claim amounts to. Langton's distinction between intrinsic, causally inert properties and causal powers is problematic, both as an interpretation of Kant, and as an independent metaphysical position. I propose a different reading of the claim that we cannot know things intrinsically. I distinguish between two ways of knowing things: in terms of their effects on other things, and as they are apart from these. I argue that knowing things' powers is knowing things in terms of effects on other things, and therefore is not knowing them as they are in themselves, and that there are textual grounds for attributing this position to Kant. -- useful bibliography of past few decades of both Kant debate and powers, properties etc metaphysics -- downloaded pdf to Note
article
jstor
books
intellectual_history
18thC
Kant
metaphysics
epistemology
causation
Hume-causation
Locke
Leibniz
noumena
phenomena
properties
essence
substance
relations
bibliography
downloaded
EF-add
august 2014 by dunnettreader
Galen Strawson - Realism and Causation | JSTOR: The Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. 37, No. 148 (Jul., 1987), pp. 253-277
august 2014 by dunnettreader
This looks like early work towards his "necessary connexion" book on Hume that challenges the standard regularity interpretation of Hume on causality. Bibliography looks useful -- downloaded pdf to Note
article
jstor
metaphysics
intellectual_history
philosophy_of_science
18thC
Hume-causation
causation
realism
scepticism
positivism
properties
laws_of_nature
powers
downloaded
EF-add
august 2014 by dunnettreader
Stuart Glennan - Aspects of Human Historiographic Explanation: A View from the Philosophy of Science (2014)
july 2014 by dunnettreader
While some philosophers of history have argued that explanations in human history are of a fundamentally different kind than explanations in the natural sciences, I shall argue that this is not the case. Human beings are part of nature, human history is part of natural history, and human historical explanation is a species of natural historical explanation. In this paper I shall use a case study from the history of the American Civil War to show the variety of close parallels between natural and human historical explanation. In both instances, I shall argue that these explanations involve narrative descriptions of causal mechanisms. I shall show how adopting a mechanistic approach to explanation can provide resources to address some important aspects of human historiographic explanation, including problems concerning event individuation, historical meaning, agency, the role of laws, and the nature of contingency. -- This is a preprint version of this chapter. The final publication is available to purchase at Springer. -- Glennan, Stuart. "Aspects of Human Historiographic Explanation: A View from the Philosophy of Science." Explanation in the Special Sciences: The Case of Biology and History. Eds. Marie I. Kaiser, Oliver R. Scholz, Daniel Plenge, and Andreas Hüttemann. Dordrecht: Springer, 2014. 273-291. -- downloaded pdf to Note
historiography
history_of_science
causation
causation-social
mechanisms-social_theory
natural_history
downloaded
EF-add
july 2014 by dunnettreader
Devin Henry - "Aristotle's Pluralistic Realism" | The Monist 94.2 (2011): 198-222
july 2014 by dunnettreader
The University of Western Ontario -- In this paper I explore Aristotle’s views on natural kinds and the compatibility of pluralism and realism, a topic that has generated considerable interest among contemporary philosophers. I argue that, when it came to zoology, Aristotle denied that there is only one way of organizing the diversity of the living world into natural kinds that will yield a single, unified system of classification. Instead, living things can be grouped and regrouped into various cross-cutting kinds on the basis of objective similarities and differences in ways that subserve the explanatory context. Since the explanatory aims of zoology are diverse and variegated, the kinds it recognizes must be equally diverse and variegated. At the same time, there are certain constraints on which kinds can be selected. And those constraints derive more from the causal structure of the world than from the proclivities of the classifier (hence the realism). This distinguishes Aristotle’s version of pluralistic realism from those contemporary versions (like Dupré’s “promiscuous realism”) that treat all or most classifications of a given domain as equally legitimate and not just a sub-set of kinds recognized by the science that studies it. By contrast, Aristotle privileges scientifically important kinds on the basis of their role in causal investigations. On this picture natural kinds are those kinds with the sort of causal structure that allows them to enter into scientific explanations. In the final section I argue that Aristotle’s zoology should remain of interest to philosophers and biologists alike insofar as it combines a pluralistic form of realism with a rank-free approach to classification. - didn't download
article
intellectual_history
Aristotle
history_of_science
philosophy_of_science
ancient_philosophy
analytical_philosophy
natural_kinds
classification
species
explanation
causation
biology
animals
EF-add
july 2014 by dunnettreader
"Adventures in Rationalism" by Michael Della Rocca
july 2014 by dunnettreader
Michael Della Rocca, Yale University -- Rationalism is the thesis that the world and all the things in the world are intelligible, through and through. Nothing happens for no reason. On the contrary, whatever takes place, whatever exists, takes place or exists for a reason. Everything. On this view there are no brute facts. Each thing that exists has a reason that is sufficient for explaining the existence of the thing. According to perhaps the most extreme implication of this view, even the world itself, the totality of all that exists, exists for a reason, has an explanation. Many philosophers today think that rationalism is a crazy view. However, this paper argues in support of rationalism, and explores its implications. -- Della Rocca, Michael (2013) "Adventures in Rationalism," Philosophic Exchange: Vol. 43: Iss. 1, Article 1. -- downloaded pdf to Note
intellectual_history
metaphysics
rationalist
causation
cosmology
Leibniz
Spinoza
downloaded
EF-add
july 2014 by dunnettreader
Brian Leiter - Science and Morality: Pragmatic Reflections on Rorty's Pragmatism (2007) :: SSRN - University of Chicago Law Review, 2007
july 2014 by dunnettreader
U of Texas Law, Public Law Research Paper No. 128 -- This is an invited commentary on Richard Rorty's Dewey Lecture, given last year at the University of Chicago Law School. "Pragmatism," says Rorty, "puts natural science on all fours with politics and art. It is one more source of suggestions about what to do with our lives." I argue that the truth in pragmatism - that the epistemic norms that help us cope are the ones on which we rely - is obscured by Rorty's promiscuous version of the doctrine, which confuses the criteria for relying on particular epistemic norms (namely, that they work for human purposes) with the content of the norms themselves (most of which make no reference to human purposes, but rather criteria like causal or explanatory power). We need presuppose no Archmiedean standpoint to conclude, as Richard Posner does, that moral inquiry is feeble in a way physics is not; we need only take seriously our best current understanding of the world, how it works, and the epistemic norms that have proven most effective in making sense of it. -- Number of Pages in PDF File: 13 -- downloaded pdf to Note
article
SSRN
intellectual_history
20thC
Rorty
pragmatism
analytical_philosophy
epistemology
Quine
Sellars
naturalism
anti-foundationalism
causation
epistemology-moral
relativism
downloaded
EF-add
july 2014 by dunnettreader
Brian Leiter - Legal Realisms, Old and New :: SSRN (2012 Seegers Lecture in Jurisprudence) - Forthcoming in Valparaiso Law Review (2013)
july 2014 by dunnettreader
“Legal Realism” now has sufficient cache that scholars from many different fields and countries compete to claim the mantle of the "Realist program": from political scientists who study judicial behavior, to the "law and society" scholars associated with the Wisconsin New Legal Realism project, to philosophers interested in a naturalized jurisprudence. But what does it mean to be a “legal realist”? What unites the two most famous “old” Legal Realisms — the American and the Scandinavian — with the “new legal realism” invoked, variously, by sociologists, anthropologists, and political scientists, among others? -- I argue that (1) American and Scandinavian Realism have almost nothing in common — indeed, that H.L.A. Hart misunderstood the latter as he did the former, and that the Scandinavians are closer to Hart and even Kelsen than they are to the Americans; (2) all Realists share skepticism about the causal efficacy of legal doctrine in explaining judicial decisions ("the Skeptical Doctrine") (though the Scandinavian skepticism on this score is not at all specific to the legal domain, encompassing all explanation in terms of norms); (3) American Realism almost entirely eschewed social-scientific methods in its defense of the Skeptical Doctrine, contrary to the impression given by much recent work by "new" legal realists; (4) the myth that the American Realists were seriously interested in social science derives mainly from two unrepresentative examples, Underhill Moore's behaviorism and Llewellyn's work with the Cheyenne Indians. -- Keywords: American legal realism, Scandinavian legal realism, Karl Llewellyn, Axel Hagerstrom, Alf Ross, naturalism, H.L.A. Hart, Hans Kelsen, judicial behavior
article
SSRN
philosophy_of_law
social_theory
intellectual_history
intellectual_history-distorted
legal_theory
legal_realism
social_sciences
anthropology
sociology_of_law
normativity
norms
causation
causation-social
positivism-legal
naturalism
social_process
judiciary
behavioralism
Hart
Kelsen
US_legal_system
downloaded
EF-add
july 2014 by dunnettreader
Matthijs Lof, Tuomas Malinen - The growth and sovereign debt correlation | vox , 25 May 2014
june 2014 by dunnettreader
Rogoff and Reinhart not only invented the tipping point, they got the causality backwards so not just no justification for austerity, the case for stimulus is stronger -- Public debt and economic growth are historically negatively correlated. This column discusses new evidence that rejects the debt-to-growth causality. After estimating the effects between debt and growth in both directions, there is no evidence that high indebtedness suppresses economic growth. The effect of growth on debt is the main driver of the negative correlation
paper
economic_theory
economic_models
macroeconomics
econometrics
sovereign_debt
public_finance
economic_growth
austerity
causation
EF-add
june 2014 by dunnettreader
JOSE R. TORRE - The Teleology of Political Economy and Moral Philosophy in the Age of the Anglo-American Enlightenment | JSTOR: Early American Studies, Vol. 8, No. 3 (Fall 2010), pp. 646-671
may 2014 by dunnettreader
"An Inward Spring of Motion and Action": The Teleology of Political Economy and Moral Philosophy in the Age of the Anglo-American Enlightenment -- The Enlightenment-era narratives of political economy and moral philosophy shared an epistemic base and theory of causation that understood the human experience as a self-realizing or immanent teleology driving toward a providential and benevolent outcome. In political economy the pursuit of personal wealth and satisfaction tended naturally to a benevolent equilibrium without the knowledge or intent of the agent. In moral philosophy the agent acted intuitively and unconsciously to satisfy immediate emotional desires that culminated in pleasure but nevertheless improved society. The teleology of both these narratives derived from a series of larger shifts in human psychology and ideas from an early modern and Reformation-era theological voluntarism to an Enlightenment-era Neoplatonic and Aristotelian theory of humanity and nature. -- downloaded pdf to Note
article
jstor
intellectual_history
18thC
British_history
Atlantic
American_colonies
Enlightenment
Scottish_Enlightenment
moral_sentiments
moral_philosophy
political_economy
causation
teleology
human_nature
moral_psychology
passions
Neoplatonism
voluntarism
Augustinian
Aristotelian
natural_philosophy
natural_law
cosmology
Providence
hedonistic
utilitarianism
bibliography
downloaded
EF-add
may 2014 by dunnettreader
Richard Marshall interview with Lisa Downing - Early Mod philosophy » 3:AM Magazine - May 2014
may 2014 by dunnettreader
Lisa Downing is the philosopher who thinks all the time about the early modern philosophers of Europe, especially 17th and 18th century philosophy, about how philosophical analysis and historical exactitude compliment each other, on adding to the canonical philosophers of the period, on why Malebranch is the closest to re-entry, and Robert Boyle, on Descartes vs Newton, on avoiding anachronism, on the dynamism of the period, on primary and secondary qualities, on resisting the idea that historical views have to be relevant, on Berkeley, on tensions in Locke, on women philosophers of the time and on rejecting the occult. This one is kick-ass! Yo!
intellectual_history
17thC
18thC
Descartes
Cartesian
Malebranche
Locke
Boyle
Berkeley
Newton
Clarke
Leibniz
Hobbes
mind-body
causation
God-attributes
Providence
mechanism
substance
metaphysics
Aristotelian
qualia
perception
natural_philosophy
free_will
Scientific_Revolution
EF-add
may 2014 by dunnettreader
Gideon Yaffe - Locke on Refraining, Suspending, and the Freedom to Will | JSTOR: History of Philosophy Quarterly, Vol. 18, No. 4 (Oct., 2001), pp. 373-391
may 2014 by dunnettreader
Downloaded pdf to Note
article
jstor
intellectual_history
17thC
British_history
Locke
free_will
mind
causation
downloaded
EF-add
may 2014 by dunnettreader
Review by: James A. Harris - Gideon Yaffe, Manifest Activity: Thomas Reid's Theory of Action | JSTOR: Philosophy, Vol. 81, No. 315 (Jan., 2006), pp. 170-175
books reviews jstor intellectual_history 18thC Scottish_Enlightenment Reid action-theory causation consciousness Newtonian mind-body free_will powers
may 2014 by dunnettreader
books reviews jstor intellectual_history 18thC Scottish_Enlightenment Reid action-theory causation consciousness Newtonian mind-body free_will powers
may 2014 by dunnettreader
Anya Plutynski, review - Hsiang-Ke Chao, Szu-Ting Chen, and Roberta L. Millstein (eds.), Mechanism and Causality in Biology and Economics // Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews // March 2014
march 2014 by dunnettreader
Reviewed by Anya Plutynski, Washington University in St. Louis -- while the themes are consistent, the authors' examples, approaches and conclusions were not. I take this to be one of the strengths of the volume: reading it is like listening in on a conversation among amicable but not always like-minded peers. Some authors place a good deal of emphasis on the utility of the mechanistic perspective in addressing core problems in philosophy of science (Darden, Carl Craver and Marie Kaiser, Steel); others see mechanism as less central to characterizing scientific explanation, method, or discovery, at least in some domains (Till Grüne-Yanoff, David Teirra and Julian Reiss). While the dividing lines are not always so sharp, one can draw some rough and general conclusions: while thinking in terms of mechanisms can be enormously important, especially in applied contexts where concerns of intervention and control dominate, there are a wide array of open philosophical questions about how we use formal models in representing dynamical behavior, what kinds of statistical tools are best at assessing causal relationships, and when we have a causal relation in general that may or may not avail itself of mechanistic thinking. It seems that when and why thinking in terms of mechanism is of use is a very context specific matter.
books
reviews
philosophy_of_science
mechanism
mechanisms-social_theory
causation
causation-evolutionary
evolutionary_biology
economic_theory
economic_models
statistics
EF-add
march 2014 by dunnettreader
Alastair Wilson, review - Stephen Mumford and Matthew Tugby (eds.), Metaphysics and Science // Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews // Feb 2014
march 2014 by dunnettreader
This volume has two main aims. One is to collect together high-quality work from the intersection of metaphysics and the philosophy of science. In this, it succeeds admirably; the essays will be essential reading for anyone working seriously on laws of nature, dispositions, natural kinds, or emergence. The second aim is to demarcate and exemplify the discipline of metaphysics of science, which the editors set out to define in their introduction. Success here is less clear-cut, and there is room for doubt about the value of the definition project.
books
reviews
philosophy_of_science
metaphysics
causation
kinds
emergence
march 2014 by dunnettreader
Brian Leiter, review - Christopher Janaway, Beyond Selflessness: Reading Nietzsche's Genealogy // Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews // (2007)
march 2014 by dunnettreader
.. this intelligent and illuminating book, which aims to defend two rather precise theses about reading Nietzsche's On the Genealogy of Morality: first, that Nietzsche's method of writing is intended to engage the reader emotionally or affectively; and second, that such affective engagement is a necessary precondition for altering the reader's views about evaluative questions -- that "without the rhetorical provocations, without the revelation of what we find gruesome, shaming, embarrassing, comforting, and heart-warming we would neither comprehend nor be able to revalue our current values". -- Janaway and I are farther apart with respect to Nietzsche's conception of human agency and freedom. Janaway takes the passage on "the sovereign individual" (GM II:2) as giving expression to Nietzsche's "positive conception of free will" as "involv[ing] acting fully within one's character, knowing its limits and capabilities, and valuing oneself for what one is rather than for one's conformity to an external standard or to what one ought to be". It seems to me a mistake, however, to read this passage as articulating a kind of ideal of agency or selfhood; in context, I think it is far more plausible to understand the passage as being wholly ironic and mocking. -- very useful re Leiter view of both Hume and Nietzsche's "science of man" based on "speculative naturalism"
books
reviews
intellectual_history
18thC
19thC
Germany
Nietzsche
Hume
naturalism
science_of_man
moral_psychology
free_will
causation
agency
EF-add
march 2014 by dunnettreader
Dermot Moran, review - Steven Crowell, Normativity and Phenomenology in Husserl and Heidegger // Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews // Feb 2014
march 2014 by dunnettreader
C Normativity and Phenomenology in Husserl and Heidegger, Cambridge University Press, 2013, 321pp., $29.99 (pbk), ISBN 9781107682559.
Reviewed by University College Dublin
Steven Crowell's latest monograph is a careful and nuanced thematic and historically grounded defense of the philosophical importance of what is now frequently called "classical" phenomenology (specifically Husserl and Heidegger) in addressing the issues of meaning, normativity, agency and first-person knowledge, topics central to contemporary analytic philosophy of mind and action. This well argued book situates Husserl and Heidegger not just at the center of contemporary debates in the philosophy of mind and action, but also as interlocutors in current disputes over normativity and practical knowledge (as found in the neo-pragmatism of John McDowell and Robert Brandom, among others), as well as the current discussions concerning first-person authority and mental content.
Crowell is not just conversant with the intricacy of the texts of Husserl and Heidegger (whom he reads with detailed documentation as in substantial agreement with one another), but also with a wide range of figures in contemporary philosophy of mind, moral psychology, and neo-pragmatism, including John Searle, Hubert Dreyfus, Alva Noë, Richard Moran (no relation), and Christine Korsgaard). In the course of his interpretations of Husserl and Heidegger, moreover, Crowell has a lot of instructive (and corrective) things to say about such issues as mental content, internalism and externalism, causation, the relation between perception and conception, the connection between self-consciousness and normativity, the transparency and immediacy of self-knowledge (in an interesting engagement with Moran) and the meaning of agency (including moral agency) in relation to Heidegger's notion of authenticity. This is a very rich, often dense but never less than lucid book that offers a systematic defense of phenomenology in the language of contemporary philosophy and thereby achieves a double objective, namely to set a new agenda for phenomenological discussion in the twenty-first century and to show why analytic philosophers would be wrong to neglect the phenomenological heritage.
books
reviews
kindle-available
philosophy
phenomenology
Husserl
Heidegger
idealism-transcendental
mind
action-theory
normativity
consciousness
responsibility
conscience
perception
causation
mind-body
agency
moral_psychology
Kant
analytical_philosophy
meaning
concepts
pragmatism
authenticity
EF-add
Reviewed by University College Dublin
Steven Crowell's latest monograph is a careful and nuanced thematic and historically grounded defense of the philosophical importance of what is now frequently called "classical" phenomenology (specifically Husserl and Heidegger) in addressing the issues of meaning, normativity, agency and first-person knowledge, topics central to contemporary analytic philosophy of mind and action. This well argued book situates Husserl and Heidegger not just at the center of contemporary debates in the philosophy of mind and action, but also as interlocutors in current disputes over normativity and practical knowledge (as found in the neo-pragmatism of John McDowell and Robert Brandom, among others), as well as the current discussions concerning first-person authority and mental content.
Crowell is not just conversant with the intricacy of the texts of Husserl and Heidegger (whom he reads with detailed documentation as in substantial agreement with one another), but also with a wide range of figures in contemporary philosophy of mind, moral psychology, and neo-pragmatism, including John Searle, Hubert Dreyfus, Alva Noë, Richard Moran (no relation), and Christine Korsgaard). In the course of his interpretations of Husserl and Heidegger, moreover, Crowell has a lot of instructive (and corrective) things to say about such issues as mental content, internalism and externalism, causation, the relation between perception and conception, the connection between self-consciousness and normativity, the transparency and immediacy of self-knowledge (in an interesting engagement with Moran) and the meaning of agency (including moral agency) in relation to Heidegger's notion of authenticity. This is a very rich, often dense but never less than lucid book that offers a systematic defense of phenomenology in the language of contemporary philosophy and thereby achieves a double objective, namely to set a new agenda for phenomenological discussion in the twenty-first century and to show why analytic philosophers would be wrong to neglect the phenomenological heritage.
march 2014 by dunnettreader
Eric D. Beinhocker : Reflexivity, complexity, and the nature of social science - Journal of Economic Methodology [Soros special issue] - Volume 20, Issue 4 - Taylor & Francis Online
january 2014 by dunnettreader
pages 330-342 -- downloaded pdf to Note -- In 1987, George Soros introduced his concepts of reflexivity and fallibility and has further developed and applied these concepts over subsequent decades. This paper attempts to build on Soros's framework, provide his concepts with a more precise definition, and put them in the context of recent thinking on complex adaptive systems. The paper proposes that systems can be classified along a ‘spectrum of complexity’ and that under specific conditions not only social systems but also natural and artificial systems can be considered ‘complex reflexive.’ The epistemological challenges associated with scientifically understanding a phenomenon stem not from whether its domain is social, natural, or artificial, but where it falls along this spectrum. Reflexive systems present particular challenges; however, evolutionary model-dependent realism provides a bridge between Soros and Popper and a potential path forward for economics.
article
philosophy_of_science
philosophy_of_social_science
epistemology
methodology
complexity
Soros
reflexivity
intentionality
evolution-as-model
Popper
scientific_method
downloaded
EF-add
systems-complex_adaptive
systems-reflexive
systems_theory
economic_theory
economic_models
EMH
rationality-economics
rational_expectations
information-markets
cognition
cognition-social
falsification
neuroscience
uncertainty
laws_of_nature
covering_laws
causation
explanation
prediction
january 2014 by dunnettreader
Kenneth P. Winkler - The New Hume I JSTOR: The Philosophical Review, Vol. 100, No. 4 (Oct., 1991), pp. 541-579
january 2014 by dunnettreader
Downloaded pdf to Note -- see next issue of Philosophical Review for correction of one sentence
article
jstor
intellectual_history
18thC
Hume
scepticism
causation
downloaded
EF-add
january 2014 by dunnettreader
Helen Beebee - Humes Old and New:response to Peter Millican: The Two Definitions and the Doctrine of Necessity | JSTOR: Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, New Series, Vol. 107 (2007), pp. 413-431
january 2014 by dunnettreader
Downloaded pdf to Note
article
jstor
intellectual_history
18thC
Hume
scepticism
causation
downloaded
EF-add
january 2014 by dunnettreader
Peter Millican - Humes Old and New: Four Fashionable Falsehoods, and One Unfashionable Truth | JSTOR: Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes, Vol. 81 (2007), pp. 163-199
january 2014 by dunnettreader
See response by Helen Beebee -- downloaded pdf to Note
article
jstor
intellectual_history
18thC
Hume
scepticism
causation
downloaded
EF-add
january 2014 by dunnettreader
Peter Millican - Hume, Causal Realism, and Causal Science | JSTOR: Mind, New Series, Vol. 118, No. 471 (Jul., 2009), pp. 647-712
january 2014 by dunnettreader
The 'New Hume' interpretation, which sees Hume as a realist about 'thick' Causal powers, has been largely motivated by his evident commitment to causal language and causal science. In this, however, it is fundamentally misguided, failing to recognise how Hume exploits his anti-realist conclusions about (upper-case) Causation precisely to support (lower-case) causal science. When critically examined, none of the standard New Humean arguments—familiar from the work of Wright, Craig, Strawson, Buckle, Kail, and others—retains any significant force against the plain evidence of Hume's texts. But the most devastating objection comes from Hume's own applications of his analysis of causation, to the questions of 'the immateriality of the soul' and 'liberty and necessity'. These show that the New Hume interpretation has misunderstood the entire purpose of his 'Chief Argument', and presented him as advocating some of the very positions he is arguing most strongly against. -- paywall Oxford Journals 7 years until jstor
article
jstor
paywall
intellectual_history
18thC
Hume
causation
scepticism
soul
free_will
determinism
EF-add
january 2014 by dunnettreader
Daniel Little - Guest post by Ruth Groff on causal powers | Understanding Society Jan 2014
january 2014 by dunnettreader
Do you have to be an Aristotelian to believe in causal powers? -- Discusses 5 separate factors that together might be construed as a coherent Aristotelian position (leaving out teleological purpose of powers) which anti-passivists may or may not share. 1. Materialism, 2. Potentiality, 3. Essential properties, 4. Emergence (whole more than sum of parts or plurality), 5. Powers as capacity for doing. She points out that both Locke and Leibniz accepted powers without Locke at least being Aristotelian. She concludes that one can coherently accept causal powers without embracing all 5, although materialism and potentiality are fairly natural fits with powers, and something along the lines of essential properties is required to differentiate what things have or are characterized by specific powers and which are not. Emergence looks to her like comfortable but not necessary fit. As asides to her main discussion of "anti-passivists" are her characterizations of Hume on causation, which seems to me typical of 20thC interpretations of Hume as arch sceptic and denier of causation - as distinct from his denial of *knowledge* as an academic sceptic and, therefore, his assertion that it's unwarranted to extend names we give to things we experience but don't understand (eg powers) to metaphysical or theological speculation. She is not taking the "academic sceptic" interpretation of Hume -- simply saying we can't explain causal powers but can only identify regularity of connection. Instead, she quotes him that "power" is meaningless -- but Hume didn't deny gravity as causal factor but rather that we couldn't explain what gravity is in an "essential" sense beyond regular connections that had predictable outcomes -- calling gravity a "power" didn't add any explanatory information to gravity's causality or enlighten us about other causally relevant features of the physical world that we also label "powers", and certainly didn't warrant willy nilly applying "power" to our metaphysical and theological fantasies.
causation-social
social_theory
causation
neo-Aristotelian
Hume-causation
emergence
scepticism
january 2014 by dunnettreader
Haskell Fain, review essay - Plausible Worlds: Possibility and Understanding in History and the Social Sciences by Geoffrey Hawthorn | JSTOR: History and Theory, Vol. 32, No. 1 (Feb., 1993), pp. 83-90
december 2013 by dunnettreader
Fain doesn't think much of the book, but provides a quite interesting potted history of the nomothetic vs ideographic "sciences", Popper-Hempel covering law, responses in 20thC analytical philosophy dealing with possible worlds and counterfactuals (eg Nelson Goodman), and overall explanation vs causation approaches to history, "events" and social sciences. Didn't download paper. May be helpful in sorting out what has Martin so riled in his Explanation of Social Action (see Kindle)
books
reviews
jstor
kindle
20thC
intellectual_history
causation
causation-social
covering_laws
social_theory
historiography
counterfactuals
epistemology
analytical_philosophy
EF-add
december 2013 by dunnettreader
Alan Donagan - Historical Explanation: The Popper-Hempel Theory Reconsidered | JSTOR: History and Theory, Vol. 4, No. 1 (1964), pp. 3-26
december 2013 by dunnettreader
See jstor summary for extensive list of citations to this article -- looks like the high water mark of positivism in history
article
jstor
social_theory
historiography
empiricism
positivism
causation
causation-social
human_nature
rational_choice
covering_laws
historicism
scientific_method
Popper
EF-add
december 2013 by dunnettreader
Thorstein Veblen - Why is Economics not an Evolutionary Science? | JSTOR - The Quarterly Journal of Economics (Jul., 1898)
december 2013 by dunnettreader
The Quarterly Journal of Economics, Vol. 12, No. 4 (Jul., 1898), pp. 373-397 -- downloaded to Note
article
social_theory
economic_theory
philosophy_of_social_science
epistemology
philosophy_of_science
Methodenstreit
methodology-qualitative
methodology-quantitative
causation-social
causation-evolutionary
causation
economic_models
intellectual_history
Veblen
downloaded
19thC
20thC
institutional_economics
historical_sociology
historical_change
historiography-19thC
change-economic
change-social
december 2013 by dunnettreader
Daniel Little - Understanding Society: What is reduction? Sept 2013
november 2013 by dunnettreader
Discusses Wimsatt re models of (good and bad) reduction in biology - paper downloaded to Note -- His article "Reductionism and its heuristics: Making methodological reductionism honest" is particularly useful (link). Wimsatt distinguishes among three varieties of reductionism in the philosophy of science: inter-level reductive explanations, same-level reductive theory succession, and eliminative reduction (448).
social_theory
ontology-social
ontology
philosophy_of_science
causation
reductionism
downloaded
EF-add
november 2013 by dunnettreader
Daniel Little - Understanding Society: Meso causes and microfoundations | September 10 2013
september 2013 by dunnettreader
In earlier posts I've paid attention to the need for microfoundations and the legitimacy of meso-level causation. And I noted that there seems to be a prima facie tension between the two views in the philosophy of social science. I believe the two are compatible if we understand the microfoundations thesis as a claim about social ontology and not about explanation, and if we interpret it in a weak rather than a strong way. Others have also found this tension to be of interest. The September issue of The Philosophy of the Social Sciences" provides a very interesting set of articles on this set of issues.
Particularly interesting is a contribution by Tuukka Kaidesoja, "Overcoming the Biases of Microfoundations: Social Mechanisms and Collective Agents".
social_theory
microfoundations
causation
mechanism
mesolevel
organizations
critical_realism
EF-add
Particularly interesting is a contribution by Tuukka Kaidesoja, "Overcoming the Biases of Microfoundations: Social Mechanisms and Collective Agents".
september 2013 by dunnettreader
Daniel Little - Understanding Society: Social mechanisms and meso-level causes September 2013
september 2013 by dunnettreader
Paper downloaded to Note -- blog post summarizes and has lots of links to useful recent lit -- (This post summarizes a paper I presented at the British Society for the Philosophy of Science Annual Meeting in 2012.)
Here and elsewhere I want to defend the theoretical possibility of attributing causal powers to meso-level social entities and structures. In this I follow a number of philosophers and sociologists, including many critical realists (e.g. Roy Bhaskar, A Realist Theory of Science and Margaret Archer, Realist Social Theory: The Morphogenetic Approach) and also the recent thinking of Dave Elder-Vass (The Causal Power of Social Structures). But I also defend the idea of an actor-centered sociology, according to which the substance of social phenomena is entirely made up of the actions, interactions, and states of mind of socially constituted individual actors. Making out both positions, and demonstrating their consistency, is the work of this paper. I refer to this position as “relative explanatory autonomy” of the meso-level. This topic is of renewed interest because of the current influence and progress of analytical sociology (Peter Hedström, Dissecting the Social: On the Principles of Analytical Sociology; Hedström and Bearman, The Oxford Handbook of Analytical Sociology ; Peter Demeulenaere, Analytical Sociology and Social Mechanisms), which offers an emphatic “no” to the question; whereas critical realists are equally firm in defending an affirmative answer to the question.
social_theory
philosophy_of_science
ontology-social
microfoundations
causation
mesolevel
mechanism
critical_realism
downloaded
EF-add
Here and elsewhere I want to defend the theoretical possibility of attributing causal powers to meso-level social entities and structures. In this I follow a number of philosophers and sociologists, including many critical realists (e.g. Roy Bhaskar, A Realist Theory of Science and Margaret Archer, Realist Social Theory: The Morphogenetic Approach) and also the recent thinking of Dave Elder-Vass (The Causal Power of Social Structures). But I also defend the idea of an actor-centered sociology, according to which the substance of social phenomena is entirely made up of the actions, interactions, and states of mind of socially constituted individual actors. Making out both positions, and demonstrating their consistency, is the work of this paper. I refer to this position as “relative explanatory autonomy” of the meso-level. This topic is of renewed interest because of the current influence and progress of analytical sociology (Peter Hedström, Dissecting the Social: On the Principles of Analytical Sociology; Hedström and Bearman, The Oxford Handbook of Analytical Sociology ; Peter Demeulenaere, Analytical Sociology and Social Mechanisms), which offers an emphatic “no” to the question; whereas critical realists are equally firm in defending an affirmative answer to the question.
september 2013 by dunnettreader
Patrick Thaddeus Jackson and Daniel H. Nexon: International theory in a post-paradigmatic era: From substantive wagers to scientific ontologies | Special Issue End of IR Theory? - European Journal of International Relations September 2013
september 2013 by dunnettreader
Concerns about the end of International Relations theory pivot around at least three different issues: the fading of the ‘paradigm wars’ associated with the 1990s and early 2000s; the general lack of any sort of ‘great debate’ sufficient to occupy the attention of large portions of the field; and claims about the vibrancy of middle-range theorizing. None of these are terribly helpful when it comes to assessing the health of International Relations theory. We argue that international theory involves scientific ontologies of world politics: topographies of entities, processes, mechanisms, and how they relate to one another. Understood this way, the state of International Relations theory looks strong: there is arguably more out there than ever before. Ironically, this cornucopia helps explain concerns regarding the end of International Relations theory. In the absence of a ‘great debate,’ let alone ways of organizing contemporary International Relations theory, this diversity descends into cacophony. We submit that three major clusters of international theory are emerging: choice-theoretic, experience-near, and social-relational. These clusters map onto two major axes of contention: (1) the degree that actors should be treated as autonomous from their environment; and (2) the importance of thickly contextual analysis. These disputes are both field-wide and high-stakes, even if we do not always recognize them as such...... Keywords: choice-theoretical, experience-near, great debates, International Relations theory, paradigms, scientific ontology, social-relational...... doi: 10.1177/1354066113495482 - European Journal of International Relations, September 2013 vol. 19 no. 3, 543-565 -- uploaded to Dropbox
article
IR_theory
social_theory
philosophy_of_science
ontology-social
networks
causation
thick_analysis
agents
downloaded
EF-add
september 2013 by dunnettreader
Paul Schuurman : Determinism and Causal Feedback Loops in Montesquieu's Explanations for the MilitaryRise and Fall of Rome (2013) | T & F Online
september 2013 by dunnettreader
British Journal for the History of Philosophy, Volume 21, Issue 3, 2013, pages 507- 528, Available online: 23 May 2013, DOI: 10.1080/09608788.2013.771612 -- Montesquieu's Considérations sur les causes de la grandeur des Romains et de leur décadence (1733/1734) is a methodological exercise in causal explanation on the meso-level applied to the subject of the military rise and fall of Rome. Rome is described as a system with contingent initial conditions that have a strong path-determining effect. Contingent and plastic initial configurations become highly determining in their subsequent operation, thanks to self-reinforcing feedback loops. Montesquieu's method seems influenced by the ruthless commitment to efficient causality and the reductionism of seventeenth-century mechanicist philosophy; but in contrast to these predecessors, he is more interested in dynamic processes than in unchangeable substances, and his use of efficient causality in the context of a system approach implies a form of holism that is lacking in his predecessors. The formal and conceptual analysis in this article is in many ways complementary with Paul Rahe's recent predominantly political analysis of the Considérations. At the same time, this article points to a problem in the works on the Enlightenment by Jonathan Israel: his account stresses a one-dimensional continuum consisting of Radical, Moderate and Counter-Enlightenment. This invites Israel to place the combined religious, political and philosophical views of each thinker on one of these three points. His scheme runs into trouble when a thinker with moderate religious and political views produces radical philosophical concepts. Montesquieu's Considérations is a case in point.
article
paywall
intellectual_history
18thC
Montesquieu
ancient_Rome
Roman_Republic
Roman_Empire
military_history
lessons-of-history
determinism
causation
social_theory
mechanism
path-dependency
historiography
Enlightenment
Radical_Enlightenment
Counter-Enlightenment
find
EF-add
september 2013 by dunnettreader
George L. Dillon: George L. Dillon Complexity and Change of Character in Neo-Classical Criticism (1974)
august 2013 by dunnettreader
JSTOR: Journal of the History of Ideas, Vol. 35, No. 1 (Jan. - Mar., 1974), pp. 51-61 -- downloaded pdf to Note
article
jstor
intellectual_history
cultural_history
literary_history
genre
historiography
biography
biography-writing
character
causation
emotions
psychology
16thC
17thC
18thC
English_lit
French_lit
self
downloaded
EF-add
august 2013 by dunnettreader
John E. Hare review: Angus Ritchie, From Morality to Metaphysics: The Theistic Implications of our Ethical Commitments // Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews August 2013
august 2013 by dunnettreader
The book looks awful but the review is quite interesting Ritchie's use of or failure to use the history of philosophy. Ritchie undertakes to show the failures of axiarchism, the view that the good has a causal role, making things to be a certain way just because it is good for them to be that way. This is a version of final causation, and is familiar to anyone who knows Aristotelian metaphysics. When Ritchie comes to discuss axiarchism without divine purposes, which is Aristotle's position, Aristotle is not mentioned. The whole move from teleology in nature (what was called in the nineteenth century 'teleonomy') to teleology confined to the purposes of designers (as in Duns Scotus, for example) is examined as though there had not been centuries of discussion about it. ..... The other quibble is about Robert M. Adams. Ritchie attributes to Adams the view that because God is loving, God will perform the most loving action (169). But Adams would deny the maximization thesis implied here. More importantly, Ritchie thinks that if we ground moral obligation in God's character as loving, that means we do not ground it in God's will. Adams would deny the dichotomy here, because he thinks that God's willing and God's character are necessarily harmonious (Finite and Infinite Goods, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999, 47f). For Adams, God does constitute our obligations by command, which is an expression of will, but it is the expression of a loving will, not an arbitrary one (except in the antique sense of 'arbitrary' in which it means 'within a person's discretion,' in Latin arbitrium).
books
reviews
theism
metaethics
evolution
God-attributes
voluntarism
causation
teleology
obligation
EF-add
august 2013 by dunnettreader
UnderstandingSociety: Causal inference and random trials | June 2013
june 2013 by dunnettreader
Nancy Cartwright re causation, this time in medical and social interventions.
Her current book Evidence-Based Policy: A Practical Guide to Doing It Better (with Jeremy Hardie) provides a different critical perspective on causal inference, this time in the context of social policy reasoning.
, C&H take issue with the conviction that random controlled trials (RCT) -- the gold standard of causal inference and experiment in clinical medicine -- provide a basis for expecting that a given policy intervention will have similar effects in the future. Their book can be read as a critique of an excessively statistical understanding of social causality, without realistic analysis of the underlying mechanisms and processes.
RCT evidence shows only that the policy worked on the circumstances tested in the study. Instead, they argue that we need to offer evidence about two additional considerations: whether the "causal principle" associated with P will remain the same in new circumstances; and whether the associated conditions necessary for the operation of this principle will be present in the new circumstances.
Cartwright doesn't put her case in these terms, but I would say that the heart of her intuition is that social outcomes are different from medical outcomes because of their inherent causal heterogeneity.
social_theory
causation
RCT
methodology
Her current book Evidence-Based Policy: A Practical Guide to Doing It Better (with Jeremy Hardie) provides a different critical perspective on causal inference, this time in the context of social policy reasoning.
, C&H take issue with the conviction that random controlled trials (RCT) -- the gold standard of causal inference and experiment in clinical medicine -- provide a basis for expecting that a given policy intervention will have similar effects in the future. Their book can be read as a critique of an excessively statistical understanding of social causality, without realistic analysis of the underlying mechanisms and processes.
RCT evidence shows only that the policy worked on the circumstances tested in the study. Instead, they argue that we need to offer evidence about two additional considerations: whether the "causal principle" associated with P will remain the same in new circumstances; and whether the associated conditions necessary for the operation of this principle will be present in the new circumstances.
Cartwright doesn't put her case in these terms, but I would say that the heart of her intuition is that social outcomes are different from medical outcomes because of their inherent causal heterogeneity.
june 2013 by dunnettreader
related tags
13thC ⊕ 16thC ⊕ 17thC ⊕ 18thC ⊕ 19thC ⊕ 20thC ⊕ academia ⊕ access_to_finance ⊕ access_to_services ⊕ action-theory ⊕ agency ⊕ agents ⊕ Albert_Magnus ⊕ American_colonies ⊕ analytical_philosophy ⊕ anatomy ⊕ ancient_philosophy ⊕ ancient_Rome ⊕ animals ⊕ anthropology ⊕ anti-foundationalism ⊕ antimonies ⊕ Aristotelian ⊕ Aristotle ⊕ article ⊕ astrology ⊕ astronomy ⊕ Atlantic ⊕ atomism ⊕ Augustinian ⊕ austerity ⊕ authenticity ⊕ banking ⊕ Bayesian ⊕ behavioralism ⊕ behavioral_economics ⊕ Berkeley ⊕ bibliography ⊕ biography ⊕ biography-writing ⊕ biology ⊕ books ⊕ Boudon ⊕ Boyle ⊕ brain ⊕ British_history ⊕ Cartesian ⊕ causation ⊖ causation-evolutionary ⊕ causation-social ⊕ change-economic ⊕ change-social ⊕ chaos_theory ⊕ character ⊕ Clarke ⊕ classification ⊕ cognition ⊕ cognition-social ⊕ cognitive_bias ⊕ complexity ⊕ complex_adaptive_systems ⊕ concepts ⊕ conference ⊕ conscience ⊕ consciousness ⊕ contingency ⊕ cosmology ⊕ Counter-Enlightenment ⊕ counterfactuals ⊕ covering_laws ⊕ creation ⊕ credit ⊕ critical_realism ⊕ cultural_history ⊕ decision_theory ⊕ demonstration ⊕ Descartes ⊕ determinism ⊕ development ⊕ development-impact ⊕ disenchantment ⊕ divine_intellect ⊕ downloaded ⊕ dualism ⊕ dynamic_attractors ⊕ econometrics ⊕ economic_growth ⊕ economic_models ⊕ economic_sociology ⊕ economic_theory ⊕ EF-add ⊕ emergence ⊕ EMH ⊕ emotions ⊕ empiricism ⊕ English_lit ⊕ Enlightenment ⊕ epistemology ⊕ epistemology-moral ⊕ epistemology-naturalism ⊕ epistemology-social ⊕ essence ⊕ Evernote ⊕ evidence ⊕ evil ⊕ evolution ⊕ evolution-as-model ⊕ evolutionary_biology ⊕ evo_psych ⊕ experimental_philosophy ⊕ explanation ⊕ fallibility ⊕ falsification ⊕ financial_access ⊕ financial_economics ⊕ financial_innovation ⊕ financial_sector_development ⊕ find ⊕ fossils ⊕ free_will ⊕ French_lit ⊕ game_theory ⊕ Gassendi ⊕ generation ⊕ genre ⊕ Germany ⊕ German_scholars ⊕ God-attributes ⊕ Goldman_Alvin ⊕ good ⊕ Hart ⊕ hedonistic ⊕ Heidegger ⊕ Herder ⊕ hermeneutics ⊕ historical_change ⊕ historical_sociology ⊕ historicism ⊕ historiography ⊕ historiography-18thC ⊕ historiography-19thC ⊕ history_of_science ⊕ Hobbes ⊕ human_nature ⊕ Hume ⊕ Hume-causation ⊕ Hume-ethics ⊕ Husserl ⊕ idealism ⊕ idealism-transcendental ⊕ individualism-methodology ⊕ inference ⊕ infinity ⊕ information-markets ⊕ Instapaper ⊕ institutional_economics ⊕ intellectual_history ⊕ intellectual_history-distorted ⊕ intentionality ⊕ intuitions ⊕ IR_theory ⊕ James_William ⊕ journals-academic ⊕ jstor ⊕ judiciary ⊕ Kant ⊕ Kelsen ⊕ Kepler ⊕ kindle ⊕ kindle-available ⊕ kinds ⊕ laws_of_nature ⊕ legal_realism ⊕ legal_theory ⊕ Leibniz ⊕ lessons-of-history ⊕ linguistics ⊕ literary_history ⊕ Locke ⊕ Locke-Essay ⊕ macroeconomics ⊕ Malebranche ⊕ mathematization ⊕ meaning ⊕ mechanism ⊕ mechanisms-social_theory ⊕ medicine ⊕ medieval_philosophy ⊕ mesolevel ⊕ metaethics ⊕ metaphysics ⊕ Methodenstreit ⊕ methodology ⊕ methodology-qualitative ⊕ methodology-quantitative ⊕ microfinance ⊕ microfoundations ⊕ microscope ⊕ military_history ⊕ mind ⊕ mind-body ⊕ monads ⊕ monism ⊕ Montesquieu ⊕ moral_philosophy ⊕ moral_psychology ⊕ moral_sentiments ⊕ motivation ⊕ narrative ⊕ narrative-contested ⊕ naturalism ⊕ natural_history ⊕ natural_kinds ⊕ natural_law ⊕ natural_philosophy ⊕ neo-Aristotelian ⊕ Neoplatonism ⊕ networks ⊕ neuroscience ⊕ Newton ⊕ Newtonian ⊕ Nietzsche ⊕ normativity ⊕ norms ⊕ noumena ⊕ obligation ⊕ ontology ⊕ ontology-social ⊕ optics ⊕ organism ⊕ organizations ⊕ paper ⊕ passions ⊕ path-dependency ⊕ paywall ⊕ perception ⊕ pharma ⊕ phenomena ⊕ phenomenology ⊕ philosophy ⊕ philosophy_of_law ⊕ philosophy_of_religion ⊕ philosophy_of_science ⊕ philosophy_of_social_science ⊕ physicalism ⊕ physics ⊕ Plato ⊕ Pliny_the_Elder ⊕ political_economy ⊕ Popper ⊕ positivism ⊕ positivism-legal ⊕ postmodern ⊕ powers ⊕ pragmatism ⊕ prediction ⊕ probability ⊕ properties ⊕ Providence ⊕ psychology ⊕ public_finance ⊕ publishing-academic ⊕ qualia ⊕ quantitative_methods ⊕ Quine ⊕ Radical_Enlightenment ⊕ rationalist ⊕ rationality ⊕ rationality-bounded ⊕ rationality-economics ⊕ rational_choice ⊕ rational_expectations ⊕ RCT ⊕ realism ⊕ reason ⊕ reductionism ⊕ reflexivity ⊕ Reid ⊕ relations ⊕ relativism ⊕ religious_belief ⊕ religious_culture ⊕ religious_history ⊕ reproduction ⊕ research ⊕ responsibility ⊕ reviews ⊕ rights-legal ⊕ risk ⊕ risk-mitigation ⊕ risk_management ⊕ Roman_Empire ⊕ Roman_Republic ⊕ Rorty ⊕ scepticism ⊕ scholastics ⊕ science-and-religion ⊕ science_of_man ⊕ scientific_culture ⊕ scientific_method ⊕ Scientific_Revolution ⊕ Scottish_Enlightenment ⊕ self ⊕ Sellars ⊕ SMEs ⊕ socialization ⊕ social_history ⊕ social_process ⊕ social_sciences ⊕ social_theory ⊕ sociology_of_knowledge ⊕ sociology_of_law ⊕ sociology_of_religion ⊕ Soros ⊕ soul ⊕ sovereign_debt ⊕ species ⊕ Spinoza ⊕ SSRN ⊕ statistics ⊕ substance ⊕ systems-complex_adaptive ⊕ systems-reflexive ⊕ systems_theory ⊕ technology ⊕ teleology ⊕ theism ⊕ theodicy ⊕ thick_analysis ⊕ uncertainty ⊕ US_legal_system ⊕ utilitarianism ⊕ utility ⊕ vagueness ⊕ Veblen ⊕ virtue ⊕ volition ⊕ voluntarism ⊕ Weber ⊕ WWI ⊕Copy this bookmark: